Kazimierz Twardowski
Owing to both historical and immanent
factors, the most popular and widespread approach to classifying views on
the relation between the soul and the body is that which emphasizes the
problem of substances as the basis of psychic and physical life. This is
a question of great metaphysical importance, taken up by the authors of
the 17th century in their world views: Descartes's dualism, Spinosa's monism,
Hobbes's materialism, Leibniz's spiritualism. Its role was also stressed
by Wundt, who held that there were three fundamental notions where metaphysics
has long sought a definition: These are the notions of substance, matter,
and the soul [Wundt 1909, 348f] - these being prominent, since all other
general principles depend in one way or another on these three concepts.
Therefore, they are the primary features of any world view. And although
Wundt's task is primarily a classification of world views, it is a classification
of views on the relation between the soul and the body as well. For Wundt,
problems concerning the relation between the soul and the body have given
rise to conflicting hypotheses about substance. [Wundt 1911, 738]. This
is not strange, in the light of Becher's remark that solving the relation
between the soul and the body is central to the problematic of world view.
[Becher 1911, 329].
The prominence of substance in the classification of views
on the relation between the soul and the body, is most clearly reflected
in its provision of the principle of classification. Höffding, for
instance, claims that, as far as the relation between the soul and the body,
between consciousness and the brain, is concerned, "there are... one
dualistic and three monistic hypotheses possible". The former assumes
that the body and the soul affect each other as "two different beings
or substances". On the other hand, according to the first monistic
hypothesis, "the soul is an aspect or product of the body". The
second contends that "the body is an aspect or product of one or more
psychic beings". The third claims in turn that the soul and the body,
consciousness and the brain, develop "as concurrent aspects of the
manifestation of one and the same being". [Höffding 1887, ch.
II. Seele und Körper]. A similar classification of views is to be found
in Eisler's philosophical dictionary, in which he cites dualism first, according
to which the soul and the body are two substances or two kinds of processes.
This he juxtaposes with the monism that finds the soul to be the essence
of a thing, whose manifestation is the body; this he calls spiritualism.
If, on the other hand, one claims that the soul is a manifestation or function
of the body, this is materialism. A monism which believes the soul and the
body to be two manifestations, two modes of existence in the same being,
is a theory of identity. [Eisler 1910, 1266].
Bain's classification is identical with Eisler's at the
outset, though it diverges further on. Bain divides views on the relation
between the soul and the body into two main categories, according to whether
they assume one or two substances to be the ultimate elements of human being.
[Bain 1874, 170f]. Again, notions of monism and dualism are emphasized.
Unfortunately, classifications that reduce views on the
relation between the soul and the body to monism or dualism make use of
terms which are largely underdetermined. And so materialism is usually numbered
among monistic views, as it recognizes only one kind of substance, namely
matter. Yet recognizing only one kind of substance may well be consistent
with presuming two kinds thereof. A well known example of such a view is
ancient materialism. Although it rejects spiritual substance as a separate
and distinct basis of mental life, it recognizes a separate kind of atoms
constituting the soul, differing from those which constitute the body. This
view has been customarily labelled dualistic materialism. It must be noted,
however, that the sense of "dualistic" here differs from that
which it acquires when we refer to Descartes' view. In Descartes' sense,
dualism refers to two different kinds of substance, whereas in ancient materialism
it refers to two different types of substance. Thus, a terminological confusion
arises whereby materialism is numbered among monistic views, despite the
existence of terms such as "dualistic materialism". Similarly,
one could also speak of dualistic spiritualism though, like materialism,
spiritualism is classified as monistic. Leibniz's spiritualism could be
termed dualistic, since it presumes differing numerical principles for the
soul and the body. The soul is always one monad, whereas each body is constituted
in a combination of monads. A certain duality or juxtaposition can be observed
here.
Yet more important than the wavering sense of dualism
is another terminological shakiness, namely that concerning monism. This
term combines two clearly different senses: at times, monism connotes a
view which recognizes only one kind of substance at other times, however,
it describes a view which recognizes only one substance. In the first sense,
materialism and spiritualism are labelled monistic, since each reduces everything
to only one kind of substance, physical or spiritual. In the second sense,
on the other hand, Spinosa's view is monistic in that it reduces everything
to one and only one substance. The former is a monism of kind, and is qualitative,
whereas the latter is a quantitative, numerical monism. The homogeneity
of substance is at issue in the first case, no matter how many substances
there are; in the second case, it is the uniqueness of substance that matters,
regardless of its kind.
Philosophers have sought to right this terminological
shakiness, both by introducing new terms and by defining existing terms
more precisely. Separate terms for a monism of kind and for numerical monism
were necessary. The word "singularism" seemed particularly apt
the only problem being to decide which monism should assume it, leaving
the term "monism" to the other.
K,lpe speaks of six different points of view used in the classification
of outlooks. The first concerns "how many principles should be assumed
for discriminating world views: possible views in this matter are usually
classified under the headings "monism", "dualism", and
"pluralism". Yet the first two names usually express qualitative
differences; singularism would be a better match for pluralism, as a purely
quantitative opposite". [Külpe 1895 - Twardowski refers here to
the 4th edition, p. 119 (ed. note)]. Thus it would seem that Külpe
wishes to rename quantitative monism "singularism", reserving
the word "monism" for qualitative monism. Our surmise is further
confirmed by one more passage on the same page; in speaking of the second
point of view, he names the qualitative principles as its characteristic
feature. Here he again places monism in the context of other approaches
[Ibid.].
However, [later] Külpe writes again that "dualists
who, like Descartes, regard the spiritual and the material factors as two
real beings, different as to their essence, may be considered pluralists.
On the other hand materialists, spiritualists, and monists may be regarded
singularists. Thus a spiritualist like Leibniz, who ascribes to all his
monads an essence homogenous in terms of quality, must be numbered among
singularists" [Twardowski refers here to the 4th edition, p. 170f (ed.
note)]. From these words it follows unambiguously that singularism is to
refer to a monism of kind rather than to a numerical monism, since in numerical
terms Leibniz is a pluralist. In other words, it is K,lpe himself who sometimes
uses the word "singularism" in the sense of a numerical monism,
and sometimes as a monism of kind. In doing so, he may contribute more to
the confusion of terms, than to their disambiguation.
The disambiguation of terminology will probably follow
the example set by Külpe's first statement: That is, the name "singularism"
will refer to numerical monism, whereas the name "monism" pur
et simple will be reserved for a monism of kind, unless it is named
unism or unitarism.
Yet this classification is also deficient, for another
reason. It was drawn up at a time when views denying the existence of substance,
especially spiritual substance, were but incipient (Hume retraction) and
were not as significant or influential as they were later to become. However,
once they attained a position on a par with views recognizing the existence
of substance, any classification of views on the relation between the soul
and the body which is based on how many (or how many different) substances
are assumed to constitute the background of mental and physical life must
prove insufficient.
It has been necessary to find a way of extending this
classification so as to include so-called actuality theories, according
to which the soul is a tissue of mental functions or acts side by side with
substantialist theories, which either see the soul as a separate substance
or reduce it to substances of some other kind. This has been achieved by
once more splitting the sense of the words "monism" and "dualism"
so as to embrace both substantialist and actuality theories. As far as the
substantialist theories are concerned, these words have retained their previous
sense; for actuality theories, "monism" and "dualism"
have taken on a new sense. Monism, for instance, refers, not to a view that
assumes one and only one substance or only one kind thereof, but a view
which takes mental and physical acts to be homologous or even identical
facts or processes. This is how notions of substantial and phenomenal monism
and dualism have come into being. [Höfler 1897, 49f]. Substantialism
is not even the only possible non-phenomenalistic view, since one can assume
a standpoint which reaches beyond phenomenalism without adhering to a substantialist
theory. Such a position is assumed by those who claim that the soul and
the body are only two sides of one and the same actual course of facts.
Thus phenomenalist monism and dualism must be juxtaposed with metaphysical
monism and dualism, with substantial monism and dualism being only special
cases thereof. [Ibid, 50].
A view on the relation between the body and the soul may
be dualistic from the phenomenalist point of view, while being monistic
in metaphysical terms, as is, for instance, spiritualism or the parallelism
cited earlier. In addition, factors of kind and number come into play. Thus,
the words "monism" and "dualism" appear in four different
senses: monism and dualism of kind, of number, metaphysical or phenomenalist.
While describing a view as monistic or dualistic, one must clarify at the
same time the sense used in each case. It is not enough, then, to call Leibniz's
spiritualism a metaphysical monism and a phenomenalist dualism; it should
be added that it is a monism of kind.
This example proves also that a distinction between numerical
monism and dualism, as well as between monism and dualism of kind, applies
in a natural way only to substantialist, or more precisely metaphysical,
monism and dualism not to phenomenalistic monism and dualism, nor to metaphysical,
non-substantial monistic or dualistic theories.
[Translated by Zofia Kolbuszewska]
[Bain 1874] A. Bain, Geist und Körper. Die Theorien ,ber ihre
gegenseitigen Beziehungen, Leipzig, Brockhaus.
[Becher 1911] E. Becher, Gehirn und Seele, Heidelberg, Winter.
[Eisler 1910] R. Eisler, Wörterbuch der philosophischen Begriffe,
Berlin, Mittler, 3rd edition.
[Höffding 1887] H. Höffding, Psychologie im Umrissen auf Grundlage
der Erfahrung, Leipzig, Fues's Verlag.
[Höfler 1897] A. Höfler, Psychologie, Wien-Prague, Tempsky.
[Külpe 1895] O. Külpe, Einleitung in die Psychologie, Leipzig,
S. Hirzel; English edition [Külpe 1973].
[Külpe 1973] O. Külpe, Outline of psychology, ed. S. Sonnenschein,
New York, Amo Press.
[Wundt 1909] W. Wundt, Einleitung in die Philosophie, Leipzig, W.
Engelmann, 5th edition.
[Wundt 1911] W. Wundt, Grundz,ge der physiologischen Psychologie,
Leipzig W. Engelmann, vol. 3, 6th edition.