| |
Brain and Consciousness:
The Ghost in
the Machines
John Smythies
Center for Brain and Cognition, U.C.S.D.
and Institute of Neurology University College, London, UK
e-mail: smythies@psy2.ucsd.edu
Journal of Scientific Exploration,
Vol. 23, No. 1, pp. 37-50, 2009
Abstract—This paper reviews four current
theories of brain-consciousness relations—classical Cartesian Dualism, the Identity
Theory, Eliminative Materialism, and a new form of Substance Dualism that includes
a modified form of the Cartesian theory. This entails a critical examination
of our basic concepts of what consciousness is, of the nature of the body image,
and the relation of phenomenal space to physical space. This investigation reaches
the same result as that attained recently by the physicist Bernard Carr (2008)—that
what is needed is a paradigm shift in our basic concepts of the geometry of
the Universe. In order to understand phenomenal consciousness we need to replace
the present four-dimensional model with a higher-dimensional structure, in which
a phenomenal space (with its contents) and physical space (with its contents)
are different cross-sections (branes) of a higher-dimensional space (the bulk).
Keywords: brain—consciousness—mechanisms—substance
dualism
Introduction
The scientific account of a person’s consciousness
and its relation to her brain that is most prominent today holds that the
brain is no more than a single vastly complex electrochemical machine. The
function of the brain is to discover what is going on in the physical world
around the organism and to use this information to guide behavior optimally
with respect to the short-term and long-term needs of the organism. The
pinnacle of this information-processing and control system is held to be
manifest as phenomenal consciousness—the world that a person’s Self experiences—the
microcosm inside the macrocosm—that is constructed by the representative
mechanisms of perception that have their terminals in the brain.
The account of brain and consciousness presented in this
essay extends this concept one stage further. Currently it is widely believed
that the physical body (plus its brain) is the only organism that a human
being possesses. However, this is not a necessary truth but only an a
priori assumption. I suggest that phenomenal consciousness is also a
highly organized and complex entity. Up to now this organization has been
accounted for either by identifying phenomenal consciousness and
its brain in various ways, or by the Cartesian denial that any such organization
exists. What is missed by this dichotomy is the possibility of a substance
dualism in which a phenomenal consciousness (a person’s ‘consciousness module’)
and its brain are two ontologically independent parts of a human organism
located in different but related spaces (in two of the parallel universes
of brane theory), and connected by causal relations (mechanism). The Cartesian
theory is a form of Substance Dualism in which one party is material and
the other is not (‘the ghost in the machine’ or ‘unextended thinking spirits’).
The key difference between the two Cartesian realms is extension in space—physical
matter is extended, mind is not. In this new theory (Material Dualism or
Extended Materialism) both realms contain material, and both are spatial.
Each is in a brane of its own, and both branes are cross-sections of a common
higher-dimensional bulk. Key differences between them are the type of material
contained in each (atoms versus phenomenal objects) and their spatial
location relative to each other. There is not one machine with its attendant
ghost: there are two machines. However, as we will see, it will be necessary
to introduce a modified form of the Cartesian theory to complete the theory
so as to explain the Self.
The traditional classical Cartesian doctrine, that humans
consist of body (including its brain) and a mind, is not fashionable in
Academia today. In its place we are witnessing a vigorous competition between
two rival theories. One is provided by the monistic mind-brain Identity
Theory of cognitive neuroscience. The other is neo-Wittgensteinian philosophy,
that holds that the answers to the mind-brain problem come from analytical
philosophy, and a study of ordinary language, not neuroscience (Bennett
& Hacker, 2003). The present essay presents arguments that suggest that
all three of these theories are mistaken.
What Phenomenal Consciousness Is
There are two main senses of ‘consciousness’ in the
current debate. The first is the medical-behavioral sense, as when the nurse
says, “The patient is recovering consciousness, Doctor.” This can be investigated
by studying those brain states that result in coma (Smythies, “The Neurochemistry
of Consciousness,” in press) and by brain imaging studies that identify
those neurons and brain areas (the neural correlates of consciousness, or
NCCs) whose functions co-vary with various states of consciousness. The
second is the phenomenal Lockean sense, in which consciousness is all
that we experience—a person’s own sensations, images, feelings, memories
and thoughts. This can be studied by introspective methods used in
psychophysics and perceptual science (as, for example, when we examine
the properties and behavior of an after-image). “For example much of our
visual consciousness presents itself as being extended, images and
afterimages having shape, size and location in the visual field, and we describe the phenomenal realm
of which we are aware as a ‘manifold’ . . .” (Allen, 2006). Subsidiary methods
study the link of consciousness to such functions as attention, as well
as to how terms like ‘see,’ ‘mind,’ ‘consciousness’ and ‘hallucination’
are used (a) in ordinary speech and (b) in a psychological laboratory. This
essay will focus on phenomenal consciousness.
Francis Crick (1994) provided good arguments against
trying at this stage to define consciousness: it is better at this
early stage in our enquiry to try our best to describe it. Schilder
(1942, 1950) introduced the useful strategy of starting this task at the
simplest level. So stretch yourself out on your bed in the dark and ask
yourself what you can observe. Most people would say at first “Nothing.”
However, further observation shows that this is not right. As Ladd (1892)
reported “Ask people what they customarily see when their eyes are closed
in a dark room and they will reply that they see nothing. Ask them to observe
more carefully and describe what they see, and they will probably speak
of a dark mass or wall before their eyes.” Schilder (1942) said, “Even with
our eyes closed, black is perceived as a spatial relation.” And Wright (1981)
states, “Blackness, as Locke knew well, and Lord Brain has reminded us,
is a positive state, i.e. it is a sensory condition of the mind’s
presence room [that is, the visual field].”
What more can we say about this black expanse that makes
up the primitive visual field? Firstly it is limited, not limitless, in
extent. It does not have a clear-cut boundary but, nevertheless, fades out
at the periphery. Its shape is roughly circular—certainly not squareish,
for example. Moreover, there is only one such expanse, not two, although
we can easily imagine what it would be like to have two or more. Galton
(1883) takes it further: “I should have emphatically declared that my field
of view in the dark was essentially of a uniform black, subject to a light
purple cloudiness and other small variations. Now, however, . . . I have
found out that this is by no means the case, but that a kaleidoscopic change
of patterns and forms is continually going on, ....”
During the earliest stage of mescaline intoxication I
have observed that these kaleidoscopic patterns are potentiated and evolve
directly into the hallucinations typical of the psychedelic state. During
sensory deprivation experiments, this black field can develop a much more
intense black color—super-black—and can become three-dimensional. “The black
curtain in front of the eyes [read ‘eyes of the body image’] gradually opens
out into a three-dimensional dark, empty space in front of the body [read
‘body image’]. The phenomenon captures one’s interest immediately, and one
wants to find out what comes next” (Lilly, 1956).
Schilder’s ‘primitive’ visual field can also be studied
by the Ganzfeld technique. A ping-pong ball is cut into two and one-half
is cupped over each eye. This results in a white and featureless visual
field that is seen as a “mist of light” or a “filmy surface” separated from
“me” by empty space (Cohen, 1957). This homogeneous Ganzfeld was reported
to be “close at hand” or “just in front of the eyes” by all Cohen’s subjects.
The modal judgment of this distance was about 2 inches.
Thus, the primitive visual field may be observed to have
a number of properties.
-
There is just one visual field.
-
This has intrinsic spatial extension (two dimensional) as well
as a three-dimensional distance from the observer. -
It has spatial properties—i.e., a center, a periphery
and an overall shape (roundish).
-
It is colored, with black as apparently the default
color.
-
There is an observer (“me”) set back by an apparent
2 inches.
The system also has a cognitive dimension. The field does
not just exist, basic or complex, but is always taken up into perception
of some kind, either in everyday life, or as part of some psychological
experiment. In the latter I typically observe its features and can name
them—e.g., “there’s a red after-image,” “that’s a veridical percept that
shows me that there is a red rose out there,” etc. Neurological lesions
show that the phenomenology and the epistemology of this system are processed
by different brain mechanisms. In associative agnosia the patient can see
perfectly well but cannot recognize what she is seeing (De Renzi, 2000).
In blindsight the patient can see nothing but can recognize (“guess” correctly)
what the object ‘out there’ is, including its color. Blindsight is mediated
by pathways that pass directly from the lateral geniculate body to the higher
visual cortex in the left occipito-temporal area by-passing the primary
visual cortex.
One must also distinguish between the Self (“me”) and
what I experience. As Maund (2008) puts it, “. . . there are at least two
aspects to knowing what it is like to have a certain experience. One concerns
what it is like to be the subject of an experience; another
aspect concerns the ‘phenomenal’ or ‘qualitative’ character of the
experience.” I will deal with what is experienced first and then return to the Self later.
When I open my eyes in the light, the visual field
changes instantly and becomes filled with organized, coherent patches of
color that I take naively to be direct views of the contents of the
world around me—what Crick (1994) called “the vivid picture of the world
that we see in front of our eyes,” and again, “Our inner visual picture
of the external world has a unity.” Broad (1923) describes the visual field as follows: “So long
as it is light and one’s eyes are open, one really is directly apprehending
something, though it is not what one uncritically takes it to be.
This something is an extended, spatially continuous, variously colored
and shaded field, which is presented as a finite but unbounded whole.”
This account of the visual field, as presenting a picture
of the external world, can be thought of as incorporating the principles
(but not of course the exact details) of the mechanism by which
television works, and has been almost uniformly rejected by contemporary
philosophers and vision scientists on the grounds that no such pictures
are to be found in the brain, and because this hypothesis leads to a
nasty infinite regress
of little green men in the head (more on this later).
In the case of somatic sensation most people still believe
that the familiar ‘body’ that they experience simply is the physical
body composed of muscles, bones and organs. The pain of a toothache is simply
in the physical tooth. As Descartes (1931) put it, “Nature also teaches
me by these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst, etc. that I am not only
lodged in my body like a pilot in a vessel, but that I am very closely united
to it, and so to speak, so intermingled with it that I seem to compose with
it one whole.”
However, observations from clinical neurology show that
this view is, in one particular, mistaken. The vessel of Descartes’ pilot
is not the physical body, but it is the body image that is composed of all
manner of somatic sensations: “The brain creates a body image, and pains,
like all bodily sensations, are parts of the body image” (Searle, 1992).
The pain of a toothache is not located in the physical tooth but in the
tooth of the body image.
Most people are familiar with the fact that individuals
who have had a limb amputated still report afterwards feeling the limb.
Philosophers tend to dismiss this as a ‘delusion’ or an ‘illusion’—i.e.,
as not ‘real.’ However, it is neither. A delusion is a false belief. The
person who says she experiences a phantom limb is telling the truth. She
does not claim to have a real limb, which would be a delusion. She reports
correctly that she has a somatic sensation. An illusion is the misperception
of a real object. A phantom limb is not the misperception of a real limb
since there is no real limb. A phantom limb is, rather, a hallucination.
It does not represent a new order of being. A phantom limb is just the old
familiar phenomenal limb that is still generated by brain mechanisms in
the absence of any input from the physical limb. The neurons that generate
it are located in the parietal cortex. Removal of this cortex abolishes
the phantom. Phantom limbs can often be moved either voluntarily or involuntarily,
as when the limb extends automatically to ‘catch’ a ball thrown at the person.
As for reality, the pain in a phantom limb is at times real enough to drive
the patient to suicide. Nor is a phantom limb some kind of learned phenomenon,
for people with congenital absence of limbs can report phantoms (Ramachandran
& Blakeslee, 1998).
Nida-Rümelin (2008) gives a good example of the confusion
of the body image and the physical body. “We see the [colors] outside
there on the thing perceived . . . when reflecting on the phenomenal
character of our own experience we are not looking inside. We are
not perceiving what is going on in our brain or looking into some inner
space” (pp. 314–315). On the contrary, phenomenal colors are only located
outside relative to the body image, and not outside
relative to the physical body. A phenomenal color is a
part of my visual field, which the evidence suggests, in my opinion, is a
part of my own organism.
However, to avoid philosophical confusion, it is better
not to say that we perceive what is going on in our brains, or in
our private phenomenal spaces, since, by definition, we should say that we
perceive only external objects. Sensations are only a part of the process
of perception, but we do not perceive sensations. Psychologists, during
the course of their experiments, can examine or observe (but not perceive)
their own sensations, veridical or hallucinatory, but that is for different
purposes. We do not say that we perceive what is going on in our brains,
not for the reason Nida-Rümelin gives, but because we cannot confuse a part
of a process with the whole process. Having sensations is the last step
in the complex representative chain of perception. Perceiving external physical
objects involves the whole chain.
Vision and Television
The current scientific account of how vision and visual
consciousness works extends from retina to cortex. A great deal is known
about how the information delivered on the retina is transposed by numerous
serial and parallel neurocomputations at all levels into the activation
of specific patterns of neuronal activity in the visual brain. In a recent
review Mesulam (1998) says that brain mechanisms help to create a highly
edited subjective version of the world. The question then remains—what is
the relation between this “highly edited subjective version of the world”
in the brain and the ever-changing contents of a phenomenal consciousness?
As Grossberg (1987) says, “When we gaze upon a scene, our brains combine
many types of locally ambiguous visual information to rapidly generate a
globally unambiguous representation of form-in-color-in-depths . . . how
do . . . multiple sources of visual information preattentively cooperate
to create a three-dimensional form?”
The visual field presents in some sense the end result
of all these neurocomputations. But how does the system convert the
buzzing activity of billions of neurons into Crick’s “our vivid internal
picture of the external world”? When I examine my visual field I can see Crick’s
point. I can readily understand the claim that it is a picture of the world
and a televisual picture at that. A ‘television’ theory of perception is
any theory that states that the visual field in consciousness is constructed
by some form of representative mechanism. An ordinary television picture
is built up by a specific mechanism—a raster in the case of older analog
systems, and pixels in the case of digital television. If I examine my
visual field I can detect no signs of grain betraying a raster or a
pixel system, but I can easily imagine what it would be like to do so.
In the case of a digital system there would be small dots in my visual
field: in the case
of an analog system there would be thin lines. Therefore, if there is such
a system, it must be extraordinarily fine grained. That is not
impossible, yet many people claim that there are insuperable difficulties to a televisual
theory of visual perception. I will therefore review these difficulties.
The Missing Pixels
One criticism of any television theory of visual
perception and phenomenal consciousness is that it says that vision ends
in a series of television images, yet, when one looks into the brain,
there are no such images to be found. The conclusion usually drawn is
that no such images exist. Therefore we should throw the TV theory out.
However, there is another conclusion that may be drawn, and that is that
these TV images are not in the brain but in the mind. This theory may be
put as follows. The key points are (1) phenomenal space and physical
space are not different aspects of the same space, but are different
spaces, or different subsections of a common higher-dimensional space.
“. . . there is equal motivation to distinguish subjective or phenomenal
space from that invoked in our physical descriptions of the world”
(Allen, 2006). “All this [the physiological account of perception] has a
consequence that has not been adequately recognized, namely that the
space in which the physical table is located must be different from the
space we know by experience” (Russell, 1948). (2) Phenomenal space is
not an empty abstract space, but has real contents, e.g., the body image
and ‘phenomenal visual scenes’ that a neurologist would call visual
sensations. (3) Phenomenal consciousness is the final step of a TV
mechanism (as defined
above). (4) The human organism (physical body + a consciousness module)
is distributed in both realms. (5) There are two types of real matter in
the cosmos—physical stuff (e.g., atoms, brains, stars) located in one space,
and mind stuff (sensations, images and thoughts) located in another space.
Both generate equally real events that interact causally in both directions.
This point requires further elaboration. One could say that minds are entities
made of mind stuff and that experienced sensations, images, thoughts, and
feelings would then be states, processes or functions of the substantial
mental system. Alternatively one could say that sensations, images, thoughts
and feelings are different kinds of mind stuff and that their coexistence
in a consciousness module makes up a substantial mind. These could perhaps
be combined with the statement that we are dealing here with a whole—a
consciousness module—made up of a number of different parts—sensations,
images, thoughts and feelings. We then have to ask, as the various
modalities of sensations, images, feelings and thoughts appear to be
somewhat different from each other, what are the attributes that (a) put
them in the same class and (b) how can these attributes be varied so
that a visual sensation can be differentiated from an auditory one and
both from a feeling or a thought? To this we could answer that the
attribute (a) they all share is to be located in the same consciousness
module (and not in the physical world) and to belong to the same Self.
Other collections of these items, of course, will be located in other
consciousness modules and will belong to a different Self. The
attributes (b) that enable us to differentiate them are firstly
their obvious qualitative differences (think of a bright red visual after-image
and a deep humming sound) and, in addition (i) that sensations are the terminal
happenings (parts, events, structures) of a representative mechanism (which
thoughts, feelings and images are not); (ii) that visual and somatic sensations
are spatially extended, whereas thoughts and feelings are not; and (iii)
the Self owns all the others, whereas none of them owns the Self (more on
the Self later).
Another important question needs to be addressed. The
theory suggests that each person has his or her own unique consciousness
module embedded in a brane. So do all consciousness modules float around,
as it were, in one common brane? Or does each consciousness module have
a brane all to itself? If we cut a number of planes out of a cube we can
confine our cuts to the cube, like cutting slices of toast out of a loaf
of bread. Or we can add extra dimensions for each slice, thus enlarging
the cube dimensionally to a tesseract and successively beyond. In this
second model the Universe has vastly more spatial dimensions than it
does in the first. There is no means of telling which is correct. This is an empirical
matter, at present beyond our reach. A Flatlander can have her physical body in plane A and her consciousness module in a second
plane B that intersects A. A second Flatlander, with his body in A, can have
his consciousness module in B, or in a third plane C, that also intersects
A, and so on for any number of Flatlanders through D to n.
Then it might be asked, if sensations, images, feelings
and thoughts turn out to be some type of material entities located in a
space of their own outside physical space, what becomes of the concept of
‘mind’? To this one can reply that none of the discussion presented so far
applies to Ryle’s (1949) dispositional concept of the nature of mind, which
is logically different from the phenomenal sense of ‘mind’ used in this
essay that describes the structures and events that can be observed by introspection,
and the entity—the Self—that is doing the observing. A suitable machine
(organism, super-computer) can be dispositionally intelligent, diligent,
tenacious, deceitful, etc., no matter what it is made of; whereas phenomenal
consciousness requires a particular structure in line with what we can introspectively
observe.
The theory of extended materialism was first formulated
by the great chemist Joseph Priestly in 1777. He first points out that the
concept of the soul, or mind, as an immaterial substance was, in 1777, a
novel idea introduced by Descartes. Before him, and to this day in Hindu
philosophy, a dualist mind or soul was thought of as an “attenuated aërial
substance” made of so fine a material as to be undetectable by the senses.
Priestly continues, using Locke’s concept of ‘idea’:
The vulgar who consider spirit
as a thin, aerial substance would be exceedingly puzzled if they
were to endeavour to realize the modern idea of a proper immaterial being,
since to them it would seem to have nothing positive in its nature,
but only a negation of properties, although disguised under the positive
appellation of spirit. To them it must appear to be the idea of
nothing at all, and to be incapable of supporting any properties.
It will not be denied but that sensations or ideas properly exist in
the soul, because it could not otherwise retain them. . . . Now whatever
ideas are in themselves, they are evidently produced by external objects,
and must therefore correspond to them; and since many of the objects or
archetypes of ideas are divisible, it necessarily follows, that the ideas
are divisible also . . . and how is it possible that a thing (be the nature
of it be as it may) that is divisible, should be contained in a substance,
be the nature of it likewise be what it may, that is indivisible.
If the archetypes of ideas have extension, the ideas
expressive of them, and actually produced by them, according to certain
mechanical laws, must have extension likewise; and therefore the mind in
which they exist, whether it be material or immaterial, must have extension
also. But how anything could have extension, and yet be immaterial, without
coinciding with our idea of mere empty space, I know not. I am therefore
bound to conclude, that the sentient principle in man, containing ideas
which certainly have parts [is] not the simple, indivisible, and immaterial
substance that some have imagined it to be; but something that has real
extension and therefore may have the other properties of matter.
Thus Priestly presents the first formulation
of a robust material dualism in which the mind (phenomenal consciousness)
is postulated to be composed of a type of matter extended in a space of
its own. As he says “The mind . . . is not immaterial substance . . . but
is something that has real extension and therefore may have the other properties
of matter.”
The next stage in the development of this type of material
dualism was taken by C. D. Broad (1923), who enquired into the nature of
the space in which sensations (sensa) may be extended.
For reasons already stated, it is impossible
that sensa should literally occupy places in scientific space, though it
may not, of course, be impossible to construct a space-like whole of more
than three dimensions, in which sensa of all kinds, and scientific objects
literally have places. If so, I suppose, that scientific space would be
one kind of section of such a quasi-space, and e.g. a visual field would be another
kind of section of the same quasi-space. (pp. 392–393)
Putting Priestly’s and Broad’s suggestions
together we get a picture of a phenomenal consciousness as a spatially extended
and material entity located outside the brain in a space of its own that
is one cross-section of a higher-dimensional space, of which another cross-section
encompasses the physical world. The next step was contributed by H. H. Price
(1953), who saw that these two entities must be connected by a new type
of causal relation that connects events in parallel universes. Further details
of this new theory were supplied by Smythies (1956). The concept that phenomenal
space and physical space are ontologically different spaces has also been
expressed by Ayer (1940), Russell (1948), Moore (1971) and Carr (2008) (and
see Smythies, 1994: 149–150, for details).
This new theory takes care of the ‘pictures in the
brain’ problem. The pictures that fill a person’s visual field are, the
theory suggests, located outside her brain in her consciousness module.
They are constructed by a TV-like mechanism. Part of this mechanism
(that functions like the computer inside a digital TV system) is located
in her brain. The other part consists of the TV screen itself (her
visual field), plus a connecting mechanism. This abstracts the
information from the brain and throws it onto the visual field (more on
this below). A similar process operates in the case of her other senses.
So we no longer have to worry about how mechanisms as different as nerve
nets in the brain and sensory fields in consciousness
could, in some sense, be identical. Experimental evidence, fatal to naïve
realism, that the brain employs information compression technology and virtual
reality mechanisms, as does TV, has been reviewed elsewhere (Smythies, “Philosophy,
Perception and Neuroscience,” in press).
The Little Green Man
This account has been criticized by some (e.g., Crick,
1994; Descartes, 1931; Ryle, 1949) on the grounds that talking of
internal pictures in this way leads to the infamous ‘homunculus’ and an
infinite regress of little green men in heads.
The argument runs as follows: We cannot allow for vision to include internal
pictures, because, if we do, we have to ask what inside the person is looking
at these pictures, and, as Crick (1994: 24) pithily put it, “trying hard
to understand what is going on.” This means that we have to posit a little
green man inside our heads, and inside that little green man’s head, there
must be another little green man, and so on.
However, as Fodor (1981) pointed out, this argument is
invalid. He says that the fact that seeing an object requires an image
in our minds does not in the least entail that experiencing the
resulting image requires the same mechanism (i.e., another picture in
the observing Self). The two processes are essentially different. The
mechanistic process that connects the retina to the visual field (i.e., extremely sophisticated television)
is quite distinct from the ostensively-indicated interaction between a
Self and its visual field.
As I have not yet discussed the Self, this, I feel, is
the point to do so. This will require us to reintroduce a modified form of
Cartesian Dualism into the theory. Some philosophers (e.g., Berkeley) believe
in the existence of the Self. As he said (1949), “How often must I repeat,
that I know or am conscious of my own being; and that myself am not my ideas,
but somewhat else, a thinking active principle that perceives, knows, wills
and operates about ideas. I know that . . . I am therefore one individual
principle, distinct from color and sound; and, for the same reason, free
from all other sensible things and inert ideas.”
Others do not believe in the existence of the Self. Here
I side with Descartes and Berkeley. Logically there cannot be experiences
without the existence of a subject they are the experiences of. However,
the Self is not located in the head of the physical body—like a pilot in
a vessel—as Descartes put it. It is rather located in the head of the body-image,
which is itself a mental entity.
Verbal definitions of the Self are hard to achieve. So,
perhaps, an ostensive definition is better. In this you tell a person to
concentrate on, e.g., an after-image and tell you its color and shape—which
she will easily be able to do. Then you can ask, during this exercise, whether
she noticed that there was more than just an after-image involved: surely
there was also her “me” doing the examining, and such a Self is not extended
in space. Likewise, in a dream there is not just a collection of dream images;
there is also a dream Self wandering around in the dream world experiencing
all that is going on therein.
So a complete account of a consciousness module describes
a complex structure with some spatially extended parts (visual and somatic
sensations and images) plus some unextended parts (thoughts and the Self).
Further Advantages of Material Dualism
These further
advantages of Material Dualism may be highlighted by comparing it with the
competition.
(i) The Identity Theory (IT) states that phenomenal entities
(events) are identical with certain neural entities (events). As we have
seen earlier, phenomenal entities have observable properties of color, shape
and movement. Their NCCs also have properties in the same categories. These
specifications of each property are different in each case. Thus, IT runs
afoul of Leibniz’s Law of the Identity of Indiscernibles, which states that
identical entities must have identical properties. NCCs certainly carry
the same information about what’s “out there” as do sensations, but they
are in different forms. The visual cortex has a topographical code (over
30 individual maps) plus a vectorial code. The visual field has only one
topographic code and no vectorial code. How could they be identical? Besides,
it is hard to accept the proposal that a familiar phenomenal object is really
just electrochemical activity in a collection of neurons. It looks
like an image on a TV screen, not a mass of neurons. Identity theorists
may hold on to their theory in the laboratory but, in everyday life, they
are naïve realists like everyone else.
The theory of Material Dualism does not have this problem.
In that theory the only thing that neurons do is to generate complex patterns
of electro-chemical activity (Smythies, 2002) that co-vary with the sensory
input, perform computations on that input modulated by memory (see below)
and generate behavior. There is no need to invent tortuous reasons whereby
they are identical with phenomenal objects, or with any ‘act of perception.’
Internally they simply do their own thing. Externally the new theory postulates
that they bear causal relations with the contents of phenomenal consciousness.
The theory presented here is essentially the same as
that presented by Carr (2008). It differs from that published by Paul Marshall
(2005), who is concerned with the nature of the higher reality experienced
by mystics. He supports a Leibnizian panpsychic idealism. In contrast, the
theory that Carr and I support is a realist theory. Nevertheless, it can
explain the facts discovered by parapsychologists (as Carr details) and
it can present a plausible account of the place of a human soul in ‘next
world’ along lines similar to those that Price (1953) proposed.
(ii) Eliminative Materialism (EM) ‘solves’ the problem
of the relation of phenomenal objects and their NNCs by denying the existence
of the former. We are asked to believe that Crick’s “vivid internal picture
of the world” does not exist and that we are merely suffering from delusions
when we claim that it does. EM theorists equate phenomenal objects with
things like phlogiston and the luminiferous ether, that do not exist either.
However, these do not provide good models. We experience phenomenal objects,
but not phlogiston and the ether: “Churchland’s systematic denials of qualia
are transparent fallacies of ambiguity” (Crooks, 2008).
The lack of plausibility of EM can further be demonstrated
as follows. The theory says we have no experience of phenomenal objects,
yet we see perfectly well. However, there are people who really do not experience
phenomenal objects. They suffer from cortical blindness due to occipital
lobe damage. There are other people who can identify external objects, but
cannot see them. They are the patients with blindsight. So a critic of EM
can claim that what EM theorists are claiming to be normal perception is
what in fact would happen in the case of a patient with occipital lobe damage
and 100% accurate blindsight. Since no one would claim that such a patient
has normal vision, it would seem that EM runs into difficulties.
Sherlock Holmes once said that, when trying to solve any
problem, one must first eliminate the impossible: then, whatever is left,
no matter how improbable, must be the truth. I suggest that Naïve Realism,
the Identity Theory and Eliminative Materialism are all impossible theories
for the reasons reviewed above. But, however startling it may appear to
‘common sense,’ material dualism is not. It contains no impossible elements.
- (i) The concept that the Universe may be composed of parallel universes
is already part of brane theory in modern physics (Carr, 2008).
- (ii) Brane theorists at present have only thought of the contents of
any universe(s) parallel to our own physical universe as being composed
of similar material (quarks, etc.). However, a parallel universe could
contain anything, including sensations and the postulated TV-like mechanism
that transduces brain states to sensations. This mechanism, if such
exists, must contain two parts. If we consider only vision, there is
(i) the part that actually constitutes the visual field carrying its
picture of the external world. This corresponds to the screen of a TV
set in that model. But a TV-like mechanism cannot consist of just a
screen, there must be (ii) a mechanism behind the screen that extracts
the requisite information from the visual cortex and delivers it to
the screen. This it could easily do, as every point in the brain is
immediately in contact with the higher-dimensional space surrounding
it—just as every point in a plane is in immediate contact with the cube
of which the plane is a cross-section. We cannot observe this mechanism
by introspection for the same reason that we cannot look through the
screen of a TV set into the works behind. And we cannot see it by vision,
as it lies in a parallel universe outside the range of light cones in
our physical space. It should be noted, however, that parallel universes
are parallel because of their location in space, not because they are
in causal isolation from each other (Price, 1953).
(iii) Physics at present only considers causal relations
between entities in one four-dimensional (4D) universe, and uses only 4D
vectors for that purpose. However, there could logically be causal
relations between events in parallel universes (Price, 1953). All that
is required are five (or greater than five) dimensional (D) vectors. An ordinary vector
is a directional line joining two points in a 3 space (or a 4 space-time).
To obtain a 5D vector, take two 4D cross-sections (A and B) of a 5 space.
Then a directional line joining any point in A to any point in B would be
a 5D vector (Smythies, 1994).
- (iv) The theory is open to experimental test (see Smythies, 1994, for
details).
- (v) The really startling feature (for stolid ‘common sense’) of material
dualism is the already-established fact that we do not experience our
own physical bodies at all. I have become so accustomed to the idea
that my oh-so-familiar ‘body,’ that I feel wrapped around me, as it
were, every moment of every waking day—Descartes’ vessel in which the
pilot is so snugly ensconced—simply is my body that it comes
as a severe shock to realize that it is not my physical body at all,
but rather an image of my body constructed by my brain. Once one has
gotten over that hurdle, the rest is easy.
Conclusion
Allen (2006) has suggested that, in order to understand consciousness
and its relation to the brain, it may be necessary to engineer a paradigm
shift in our concepts of space and time. Penrose (1989: 144) stated “It
is my opinion that our present pictures of reality, particularly in relation
to the nature of time, is due for a grand shakeup—even greater, perhaps
than that which has already been provided by present-day relativity and
quantum mechanics.” Carr (2008) and I suggest that such a player is already
on the stage. The fact that this player has taken so long to appear may
be traced in part to the fact that higher-dimensional geometry was not available
to Joseph Priestly in 1777.
References
Allen, S. R. (2006). A space
oddity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13, 61–82.
Ayer, A. J. (1940). The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge.
New York:
Macmillan.
Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience.
Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Berkeley, G. (1949). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonus. In Luce,
A. A., & Jessup, J. E. (Eds.), The Works of George Berkeley (p. 233).
London: Nelson.
Broad, C. D. (1923). Scientific Thought. London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Carr, B. (2008). Worlds apart. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical
Research, 59, 1–96.
Cohen, W. C. (1957). Spatial and textural characterization of the
Ganzfeld. American Journal of Psychology, 70, 403–410.
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribner.
Crooks, M. (2008). The Churchland’s war on qualia. In Wright, E. (Ed.),
The Case for Qualia (pp. 203–222). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
De Renzi, E. (2000). Disorders of visual recognition.
Seminars in
Neurology, 20, 479–485.
Descartes, R. (1931). Meditation VI. In Haldane, E. S., & Ros, G. R.
T. (Eds.), The Philosophical Works of Descartes (p. 192). New York:
Dover.
Fodor, J. A. (1981). Imagistic representation. In Block, N. (Ed.),
Imagery (p. 77). New York: Bradford.
Galton, F. (1883). Enquries into Human Faculty.
London: Macmillan.
Grossberg, S. (1987). Cortical dynamics of three-dimensional form, color
and brightness perception. Perception and Psychophysics, 41, 87–116.
Ladd, G. T. (1892). Contribution to the psychology of visual dreams.
Mind, 1(new series), 299–304.
Lilly, J. C. (1956). Mental effects of reduction of ordinary levels of
physical stimuli on intact, healthy persons. Psychiatric Research Reports,
5, 1–29.
Marshall, P. (2005). Mystical Encounters with the Natural World. Experiences
and Explanations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Maund, J. B. (2008). A defense of qualia in the strong sense. In Wright,
E. (Ed.), The Case for Qualia (pp. 269–284). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Mesulam, M. (1998). From sensation to cognition. Brain, 121, 1013–1052.
Moore, G. E. (1971). Philosophical Studies. New York: Harcourt
& Brace.
Nida-Rümelin, M. (2008). Phenomenal character and the transparency of
experience. In Wright, E. (Ed.), The Case for Qualia (pp. 309–324).
Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.
Penrose, R. (1989). The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Price, H. H. (1953). Survival and the idea of another world.
Proceedings
of the Society for Psychical Research, 50, 1–25.
Priestly, J. (1777). Disquisitions
Relating to Matter and Spirit. London: J. Johnson.
Ramachandran, V., & Blakeslee, S. (1998). Phantoms
in the Brain. New York: HarperCollins.
Russell, B. (1948). Human Knowledge. Its Scope and
Limits. London: Allen & Unwin.
Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. London:
Hutchinson.
Schilder, P. (1942). Mind. Perception and Thought
in their Constructive Aspects. New York: Columbia University Press.
Schilder, P. (1950). The Image and Appearance of the
Human Body. New York: Columbia University Press.
Searle, J. R. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Smythies, J. (1956). Analysis of Perception. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Smythies, J. (1994). The Walls of Plato’s Cave.
Aldershot, UK: Avebury.
Smythies, J. (2002). The Dynamic Neuron. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Smythies, J. (in press). Philosophy, perception and neuroscience.
Perception.
Smythies, J. (in press). The neurochemistry of consciousness.
Elsevier Encyclopedia of Consciousness.
Wright, E. (1981). Yet more on non-epistemic seeing.
Mind, 90, 57–92.
(pdf version)
|