Five Dangers of Materialism

JON MILLS

Mills, Jon (in press). Five Dangers of Materialism.
Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs (Feb 2002) 5
.
From http://www.processpsychology.com/new-articles/Materialism2.htm, as published

Abstract

In the boon of medical, scientific, and technological progress, materialism has gained increasing explanatory power in deciphering the enigma of mind. But with the proliferation and acceptance of cognitive science, psychic reality has been largely reduced to a physical ontology. In this article, I explore the ground, scope, and limits to the materialist framework and show that while bio-neurochemical-physiology is a necessary condition for mental functioning, it is far from being a sufficient condition for adequately explaining the human being. This becomes especially significant when examining the question of selfhood, freedom, personal autonomy, and the phenomenal quality of the lived experience.

 

Contemporary theories in cognitive science and the philosophy of mind lend burgeoning support for the materialist position regarding the mind-body problem. That is, naturalism, physicalism, and material monism are the preferred theories that explain the relationship between mental processes and physical brain states. While dualist and spiritualist approaches offer counter-arguments to materialism (Vendler, 1994; Warner, 1994), the preponderance of current research in the philosophical, natural, and social sciences concludes that mental states are nothing but physical states (Armstrong, 1968; Bickle, 1998; Churchland, 1981; Dennett, 1991; Dretske, 1995; Searle, 1994). From these accounts, mind is brain.

Throughout this article, I highlight five central dangers associated with materialism that ultimately result in (1) the displacement of an ontology of consciousness, (2) a simplistic and fallacious view of causality, (3) the loss of free will, (4) renunciation of the self, and (5) questionable judgments concerning social valuation practices. I will attempt to demonstrate that the physicalist position eliminates the possibility of free agency and fails to adequately account for psychic holism.

The Spectrum of Materialism

Dating as far back as Democritus and Epicurus, who conceived of nature as being composed of changeless atoms as indivisible material particles in empty space, to the scientific naturalism of Thomas Hobbes, materialism has become the most popular contemporary perspective on the nature and character of mind-brain dependence (Bechtel, 1988). There are sundry forms of materialism, yet it is important to note that not even materialists can find unified agreement on what constitutes a definition of materialism. Most materialists insist that nothing but matter in motion exists. Any reference to consciousness, psyche, soul, spirit, or anything denoting mental life is nothing but active matter. Another extreme is epiphenomenalism, which is the belief that mind does exist but is caused by and emerges out of material changes which remains completely dependent on matter. Consciousness is a by-product of material-efficient causal forces and is itself causally impotent: mind has no causal efficacy of its own. All materialists would agree that immaterial agencies or entities do not exist: spirits, ghosts, angels, and demons are illusory. This often leads to the conclusion that there is no God(s) or a supernatural realm, and if these so-called non-material entities are purported to exist, they would be characterized in naturalized terms.

These accounts of materialism may be said to conform to three theses: (1) The identification thesis: mind is identified as nothing more than physical states and processes of the brain and central nervous system; (2) The explanation thesis: all human and animal behavior is best and most fully explained by physicalistic interpretations, i.e. through neuro-chemistry and neurophysiology; and (3) The exclusion thesis: there are no powers or properties to the mind that no physical object or system can possess. All mental activity, thought, and action is physically governed and excludes non-materialistic accounts of mental phenomena (Graham, 1993, pp. 128-129).

The most sophisticated form of materialism in my opinion is non-reductive materialism. Here the claim is that the phenomenology of consciousness--referred to as "qualia" or the lived experience--cannot be adequately explained from physicalistic accounts. Hence, assertions about the ontological status of consciousness are bracketed. But it is often the case that non-reductive materialist attempts to bracket or neutralize the ontological status of mind ultimately evade the metaphysical question that is precisely at issue--"Is the mind merely brain?" Even the term 'non-reductive materialism' is itself an oxymoron: substance is reducible matter. While non-reductive materialists claim that mental phenomena (i.e. the appearance of consciousness) cannot be adequately explained by appealing to physical brain states alone, the tacit ontological belief is that mind at bottom is the unification of biological-neurochemical-physical brain processes.

Recent definitions of materialism which have come into vogue within contemporary philosophy of mind include the view that, what is material is anything that perceives or exists in space and time. Flew (1984), among others, points out that the precise meaning and status of the materialist doctrine is far from clear. What are the properties, attributes, or qualities that matter can, cannot, or must possess? Furthermore, what are its essential properties? Is there a distinction to be made between its existence, being, and essence, its occurrence and phenomenology, its appearance and reality? What is the exact nature of how matter extends in space and time, the forces that operate on it, and how consciousness--itself conceived as matter--perceives and understands its dependence on it? What are the exact mechanisms by which thought occurs, and how do we know? How is it that we cannot directly intuit, feel, observe, or recognize those mechanisms or processes when they are occurring in our own minds? The range of attempted and possible answers to these questions makes materialism an ambiguous group of precepts rather than a unified doctrine.

One thing is clear about materialism: it is a reaction against and rejection of Cartesian dualism that posits a non-extended "thinking substance" which is associated with an immaterial mind (Descartes, 1641). It is worth noting, however, that there are many forms of dualism ranging from the Platonic distinction between appearance and reality, Kant's separation of phenomena from noumena, the ontological distinctions between being and essence, the dialectically opposed forces and manifestations of consciousness, to the epistemological chasms between the knowing subject and object. It is not my intention to defend ontological dualism, but only to show that materialist conceptions of mind pose many problems for understanding the complex psychological, psychosocial, and ontological configurations that constitute the human condition.

Rather than explicate the multitude of materialist positions ranging from identity theories (Armstrong, 1968; Lewis, 1966; Place, 1956), functionalism (Levin, 1986; Putnam, 1967; Smart, 1962; Sober, 1985), supervenience (Teller, 1983), eliminativism (Churchland, 1981; Stich, 1994), representationalism (Dretske, 1988, 1995; Fodor, 1987, 1998), to anomalous monism (Davidson, 1980), I will refer to the materialist position collectively which includes the following characteristics as operationally defined:

(I) Physical Reductionism: (a) all mental states are simply physical states in the brain; there is nothing 'over and above' biological-neurochemical-physiological structures, processes, and evolutionary pressures; (b) All mental events, properties, or processes arise out of physical preconditions whereby (c) the organism is conceived of as a matter-energy system composed solely of active material properties or substances reified through material-efficient causal attributions. (II) Naturalism, which I define as (a) the belief that all knowledge comes from physical conditions governed by natural causal laws based upon an empirical epistemology; (b) supports realism,(1) which is often (but not always) incompatible with a priori truths or transcendental idealist positions; (c) is a form of positivism, in that truth claims about reality are quantifiable facts that can be directly observed, measured, or verified within systematic science relying on experience, experimentation, and rational methods of inquiry; (d) is anti-supernaturalistic, anti-theological, and anti-metaphysical (despite its metaphysical consequences); (e) is pro-scientific, i.e. all natural phenomena are adequately explained or are in principle explainable through scientific methodology; and (f) displays tendencies toward non-teleological, non-anthropomorphic, and non-animistic explanations.

If materialism is going to make such ontological assertions, then it must be able to coherently defend its own self-imposed assumptions without begging the question. It becomes our task to ferret out the philosophical, humanistic, and ethical implications of the materialist project and expose the conundrums it generates if we are going to properly understand the question of mind. I will attempt to show that psychic holism becomes an alternative paradigm to the materialist position which more successfully addresses the multifaceted domains of mental processes, personal experience, and discourse surrounding mind-body dependence without succumbing to a reductive metaphysics.

The Naturalistic Fallacy

Freud (1900) admonishes us to "avoid the temptation to determine psychical locality in any anatomical fashion" (p. 536), insisting that the mind should not be reduced to "anatomical, chemical or physiological" properties (1916-1917, p. 21). Materialists, on the other hand, are dogmatic in their insistence that all mental events are ultimately reducible to physical events or brain states in the organism. Thus, physical reductionism is the sine qua non of materialism. Teller (1983) summarizes this position nicely: "Everything . . . is at bottom physical." In other words, there is no mind, only brain. One might ask materialists: "How do you know that?" To justify their claims, they will inevitably rely upon science, empirical psychology, the bare appeal to sensible and tangible experience, and/or naturalized or evolutionary accounts of epistemology (see Quine, 1969a; Vollmer, 1975; Wuketits, 1990). While science has its legitimate status, it must first establish a coherent criterion for truth. To fall back on the very criterion that it must set out to prove simply begs the question and envelopes materialist justifications in circularity.

Many criticisms have been launched on naturalized epistemology for (1) its attempt to naturalize mental notions of intentionality in materialistic and physically reductive terms, (2) its presupposition of a realist notion of truth, (3) its positivistic structure, and (4) its tendency to collapse into cultural relativism. Putnam (1983) charges that naturalized epistemology presupposes a metaphysical realism and a correspondence theory of truth in that truth corresponds to the "facts." He ultimately argues that this notion is incoherent, whereby "truth" is relevant to one's scheme of describing and explaining physical phenomena, hence embedded in a social language practice that determines how truth is to be defined and measured. This metaphysical assumption postulates a set of "ultimate" objects that are "absolute" and can be "objectively" measured, hence are "real" which essentially tries to revive the whole failed enterprise of the realism-anti-realism debate. Because realism and correspondence theory presuppose knowledge of an object world independent of the subject, such postulation becomes a meaningless proposition when one cannot talk about objectivity without importing subjectivity. It was Kant, followed by the German Idealism of Fichte and Hegel, who cogently demonstrated that the a priori structures of subjectivity make objectivity possible.

Post-structural and linguistic accounts characteristic of postmodernism maintain that truth claims are constructed by historical contingencies and socially defined language practices: our identification of Truth conforms to current rationally accepted standards of truth. From this account, any talk of absolute knowledge that exists objectively--as if it inheres as a property in an object independent of the subject--is vacuous. All interpretation rests on a theory of language, therefore objectivity is always interpreted through subjectivity. Yet language is instantiated in a social ontology and determines the definition of objectivity. However, what is agreed upon within a social context of linguistic practices and custom is determined by a collection of subjects. Traditionally, arguments against realism come from a priori epistemology and semantics, or theories of meaning. This strategy typically applies a theory of meaning or a philosophy of language to critique and abnegate any metaphysical claims to truth that naturalism holds, thus bringing into doubt serious questions about any mind-independent realms of existence. From this perspective, realism is an issue of interpretation, hence hermeneutics, instantiated in linguistic, semantic, and social practices. Even facts are language-formulable facts, and can be semantically captured in language-formulated truth (Dancy & Sosa, 1992, p. 188). This claim is that epistemically, naturalized accounts cannot make such realist assertions of mind.

Some philosophers such as Wittgenstein and Derrida seem to renounce (or perhaps elude) the whole debate itself. While Derrida deconstructs the distinction between the inner and the outer and treats them equiprimordially, from a Wittgensteinian stance, the whole debate becomes a "language game" (see Post, 1991). Because there are many equally privileged ways of communicating, each language has its own rules and vocabulary that determine what we are talking about within a social context. Therefore, no linguistic practice captures the ultimate structure of reality including the nature of mind. Absolute naturalized claims about the being and essence of mind become a naturalistic fallacy. This is the tendency to believe that a complex whole is identical or reducible to its parts, causes, and natural origins, and that the mind's complexity may be entirely explained by appealing to such naturalistic conditions.

Notions of truth and rational acceptability are relative to social language practices within a particular cultural context. "Reason is always relative to context and institution" and "the ideal language," "inductive logic," and "the empiricist criterion of significance" are "fantasies of the positivist" (Putnum, 1983, p. 358). Furthermore, reason is informed by the cultural norms that determine what naturalistic views will be. Truth--the only notion of truth one can understand--is then defined by the norms of one's culture and the cultural criteria that is socially imposed. If left unchecked, the politicalization and privileged discourse of scientific naturalism can lead to a form of cultural imperialism--My culture (truth) is better than yours!

The Destruction of an Ontology of Consciousness

Materialist conceptions of mind are highly problematic for several reasons. First of all the individual is reduced to physical substance alone which gives rise to an organismic and in some cases, mechanistic views of the human being. By reducing the psyche to matter, an ontology of consciousness is displaced. That is, there is no distinct ontological status to mental events; psychic processes and properties are merely physical properties within a functional system that constitutes the organism. The transcendental properties of the mental are reduced to atomic and sub-atomic particles within a closed system of energetics constituted through quantum mechanics. In this sense, mind does not direct consciousness or action, matter does. In short, the human being is reduced to a thing--a reified biological machine engineered by evolution and stimulated by the environment. This approach can potentially lead to a very dehumanizing account of the individual. The intrinsic uniqueness of individuality, personality, and the phenomenology of psychical experience collapses in reductionism. By making the human being merely an organism, one has stripped the uniquely personal and idiosyncratic dimensions of selfhood down to biology. While this ideology has its rudiments in natural science and evolutionary biology, from this standpoint, consciousness does not exist; that is, consciousness, intentionality, the phenomenal experience, qualia, the 'aboutness' or 'what it's like' to experience something and to live is reduced to changes in brain states engulfed in a language describing physical processes alone. Within this context, all conscious experience and behavior is a functional (and at times mechanical) operation that is organized within a systemic structure. What it means to be human and the existential questions and dilemmas that populate mental life are abandoned to sterile scientific depictions of animate organic matter. Although materialist theories vary in conceptual depth and locution, in the end there is no metaphysical mind, only physical-energetic substance.

Simplicity and Causal Fallacies

Materialism ultimately rests on a simplistic view of causality which is inherently biased and conforms to the empirical positivist tradition: namely, psychic reality is that which is directly observable, measurable, and quantifiable, thus constituted as fact. We owe this to the law of parsimony, or Ockham's razor. The virtue of simplicity is intended to be in the service of economy; that is, anything intelligible can be explained in material terms. Abstract theories of complexity and ambiguity are less economical and do not neatly 'fit' into ordinary belief systems; therefore, simplicity is preferred to complexity. However, the simplest explanation does not mean it is the most accurate. This position has been applied in the following way: "If one cannot observe it or measure it, it does not exist." In my view, the value of simplicity has been abused. There is no value in reducing the human being to a thing. While the value of parsimony is appropriate for various types of social, professional, and pragmatic discourse, the qualitative aspect of what it is like to be human is sacrificed. Cognitive science today is content with explaining consciousness as experiential changes in brain states which can in part be observed, measured, and quantifiably verified. Observation is one thing, but to make the generalized claim: "That is all there is!" is epistemically problematic. This positivistic account presupposes a 'God's eye' view of reality and thus makes a sweeping metaphysical judgment.

Materialism fallaciously believes that if psychic events are realized physically, then their tenets are proved. At the very least, materialists are obliged to take an agnostic position with regards to an ontology of consciousness. Just because one cannot directly observe or measure conscious phenomena, this does not mean that neurophysiology is all there is. As previously mentioned, this is a naturalistic or reductive fallacy. The very idea of the mental is that it is something that is not tangible, it is literally no-thing, hence psychical. This is not to deny the interdependence and interpenetration of mind and body: while physical processes and properties are a necessary condition of mind, it is far from being a sufficient condition. Mind is embodied or instantiated physically, but by virtue of its transcendental and elusive functions and properties, it cannot be spatially localized or dissected. Most materialists want to eliminate this stance as a viable possibility and hold allegiance to a simple economy--that which is real is something that is tangible. This fixation with making metaphysical and epistemic pronouncements based on tangible evidence in the service of economy jeopardizes the integrity of psychical reality.

Another pitfall of the materialist position is the simplistic notion of causality as physical reduction. Thus, materialism relies on the interaction of two primary causal attributions: (1) physical causation and (2) environmental determinism. This position insists that the human being is, in Aristotelian terminology, the conglomeration of material and efficient causes: mind is caused by the matter or physical substance it is made of as well as causally affected by the material forces that constitute the flux of environmental events. This is the case for the most unrefined materialist positions such as the type-type identity theory to the more sophisticated functional monist approaches. It boils down to (a) the physical causing all mental events, thus instituting force and motion that bring about effects, and (b) environmental contingencies that cause the organism to respond to a stimulus prior to the effect in time. This is the theoretical foundation of most materialist theories as well as American behaviorism which espouses the S-R paradigm of psychological processes.(2) In other words, some stimulus (whether internal or external) is prior to a response (whether it be changes in brain states, neurochemical networks and patterns of activity, or behavioral output due to environmental variables), thereby causing physiological, cognitive, and behavioral changes in the organism.

For example, early distinguished pioneers such as Armstrong and Lewis assign causal attributions to mental states which therefore direct behavior. However, mental events are physically realized and caused by sensory input, thus environmentally determined as well. Functionalism, on the other hand, championed by Putnam and today's contemporaries, more successfully argues for an elaborate organization of mental life (e.g., a functional physical system directs the body and consciousness via CNS sensory inputs and motor outputs, thereby producing changes in neurochemical patterns of brain activity and biophysiological structures that parallel a cybernetic machine of input-output operations). Despite these sophisticated and cogent strategies, the dynamic processes and properties of mind arise from physical substance, hence are reductionistic and physically determined. This position also holds true for certain dualist perspectives such as epiphenomenalism and the "qualia freaks." Ultimately, all mental properties arise out of matter, thereby, they belong to it and have no causal powers over physical states. Where Jackson (1982) rejects physicalism due to epiphenomenal qualia, nevertheless, consciousness is rendered causally impotent. Thus, we are biologically pre-wired and caused by environmental conditioning based on various propositional expectancies. If one espouses this view, the human being is the product of biology and the environment, nothing more.

With the exception of teleological functionalism, which employs a formal and final causal thesis, materialist theories are essentially reductive. Even with teleological functionalism advanced by Sober (1985), he ultimately supports a biological teleology in that the functional organism is purposeful in its organization and behavior. In the end, this position is also a physical reductionism for the purposeful behavior has its source in biology whose aim is functionally motivated. While an organism can have telic organization, it does not require the organism to be self-directed or have an active agent doing the directing. For example, a heart has a telos; its function is to pump blood. This is reminiscent of Freudian drive theory in that a drive (Trieb) has a functional telos but does not think; it is merely oriented toward tension reduction in the service of pleasure, or in this case, functional adaptation to biological and environmental demands.

In espousing reductive causality, materialism ignores the multicausal processes and over-determined forces of mind that, I argue, can never be exactly pinpointed as empirical science wants to profess. In David Hume's (1748) seminal work, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, he shows that temporal sequence does not necessarily establish causal connection. In other words, the mere occurrence of event Z after event Y does not provide sufficient grounds for claiming that event Y caused event Z. Causality can never be ascertained with unequivocal precision or isolated as distinct or independent physical events without accounting for the multiple over-determining forces that comprise causal complexity. For example, if I strike a match to light a fire, one could say that the physical-chemical properties of the match caused the fire (material cause), or that my action of striking the match caused the fire (efficient cause), or that the natural elements of the physical surroundings such as the arid temperature, wind velocity, dryness of the wood, etc. caused the fire (formal cause), or that my volitional intention and purposeful behavior caused the fire (final cause), or that all these conditions must be present in interactional causal harmony. Aristotle's meta-causal theory allows us to break down the constituents of causal conditions and events, but it would be a category mistake to simply reduce teleology to physical necessity alone.

In the service of parsimony or simplicity, the materialist insistence on physical ontology selectively ignores the multitudinous and over-determined processes a meta-causal theory of explanation affords. This becomes particularly germane to the question of determination, purpose, intentionality, and choice. Maintaining a physical ontology of consciousness has even further pernicious repercussions when examining the question of freedom.

Loss of Freedom

Reliance on material and efficient causal explanations, the over-valuation of simplicity à la Ockham's razor, and consequently, physical reductionism, completely eliminates any possibility of free will. From this standpoint, the human being is not free. This position is summarized by the exclusion thesis which posits that human beings have no properties or mental powers which no object or physical system can possess (Graham, 1993). Thus, if free will is a mental process or property, and no physical system is free, then we do not possess free choice and are consequently not free. This simplicity denies the possibility of final causal determinants and transcendental teleology characteristic of free agents. Agency is here defined as a subject who is telic, purposeful, and self-directed via choices and deliberation in judgements constituting self-conscious activity. Therefore, thoughts, volitional intentions, and behaviors are the activities of the will: freedom is ultimately defined as the ability to choose or be otherwise. Freedom, however, is not merely restricted to choice, it also encompasses the structural organization of the individual doing the choosing, namely the agent. In short, agency, free will, intentionality, and final causality (e.g., choosing the grounds for the sake of which to behave) is problematic for the materialist, for physical matter is caused rather than being freely causal.

Several philosophers have tried to give an adequate account of free will for the materialist position (Davidson, 1980; Dennett, 1984; Levin, 1979; Thalberg, 1983). Levin (1979) argues that materialism is compatible with free will, since he defines freedom as "doing what you want to do" (p. 228). However, materialists have a proclivity to define freedom in terms of action rather than agency. Levin continues: "one can be free even if one's acts are caused by wants, and one's wants are caused by other factors out of one's control" (p. 228). It is one thing to have control over one's actions that are "unconstrained" by external forces, yet it is another thing to say that one's thoughts or volitional intentions are caused by something outside of one's control. Within this naturalistic framework, free choice is based upon external contingencies and physical states in the organism. Thoughts and actions cannot be freely chosen if they are caused by preceding events that are environmentally or physically determined. For the materialist, desire and choice is not freely acquired: it is imposed upon the organism by intrinsic and extrinsic forces. Freedom involves the intentional states of the individual, not just actions, in that choice is defined as "I could have done or thought otherwise!" This is not the case if choice is directed by a functional system where matter causes mental events. Materialists have a difficult time explaining why we have the ability to freely choose the next thought we wish to think. Therefore, the locus of freedom resides in the agent's ability to freely will and determine one's own thoughts and actions.

Davidson (1980) attempts to account for a non-reductive materialism by claiming that the mental is anomalous for there are no precise or discernible laws that account for mental events. In other words, there are no laws connecting propositional attitudes with brain states.(3) However, the materialist's response to Davidson is that each propositional attitude might in fact be a complex brain state or network of processes, which he even seems willing to concede. Putnam (1975) also proposed the notion of "multiple realizability" of mental states as an anti-reductionist response to psychoneural identity theory. This position is also taken up by Fodor (1974) who argues that social sciences are generally irreducible to physical theory. Recently, Horgan (1994) has proposed a non-reductive materialism where he denies that mentalistic psychology can be reducible to neurobiology. He maintains that reductionism would be disproved if intentional mental state-types could be physically realized in multifarious ways. By adopting a realization-neutrality posture, the ontology of intentional states of consciousness may be preserved within a framework that gives psychological processes and properties explanatory power and autonomy.

Post (1987, 1995) and Dennett (1991) offer sophisticated non-reductive material accounts of mental phenomena that take into account the natural-selective history of ancestral organisms within their specific cultural environments. From these perspectives, the phenomenology of mind is better construed as adaptions, which are not rigidly reduced to bio-neurochemical-physiological brain processes, but rather further consist of natural-selective pressures operating on ancestral organisms over long periods of time. The usual reductive accounts, especially those insistent on individualistic and synchronic reductions, do not adequately address these evolutionary and cultural adaptations. Hence these types of materialists would hold reservations about characterizing the mind as an energy-matter system simply because some key mental properties are not sufficiently understood by physicalist paradigms.

Because non-reductive materialists acknowledge they have difficulty in accounting for certain aspects of mental reality, this leaves open the possibility for psychical interpretations of mental events that exist and manifest apart from or are at least co-extensive with physical brain processes. Essentially, this form of materialism holds an agnostic stance toward some possible form of dualism or compatiblism. But when we follow this line of thinking through to its end, there really is no materialist position that is truly non-reductive, for any position that ultimately posits mental life in physical-evolutionary terms is reductionistic. Evolutionary adaptations are realized physical mutations of brain processes and organismic structures. Thus, there is no such thing as non-reductive materialism: it is merely a myth (Kim, 1994). The burden of proof lies on the shoulders of those materialists who wish to account for freedom within an entirely materialist framework.

Charles Hanly's (1979) solution to the question of materialism is to offer a compatiblist framework of psychic determinism. While deterministic forces populate mental life, the difference between a free and a compelled act is due to the nature of its causes, for all acts are caused. Therefore, the concepts of will, intentionality, autonomy, and responsibility, may be seen as compatible operations within the mind in which the notion of freedom is preserved within a determinist model. Here the point is, that while psychic life is bound to the necessity of its natural configurations, the psyche may still operate as a freely determining self-directed agent.

Dretske (1988) and Dennett (1981) attempt to explain meaning, intentionality, 'aboutness' and the 'what it's like' aspect of qualia by placing primacy on the internal states of the organism that cause experience and behavior due to the internal organization of the functional states, rather than assigning causal attributions to the environment. From this perspective, the structure of the organism appears to have free will; it interacts with the surround and structures meaning within its functional framework, assigns experience a job, indicates a role for it, thus allegedly producing meaning and choosing the grounds for the sake of which to behave. By making a functional organism assign meaning to experience, they preserve the self as a self-directed agent, so it seems. Despite this, freedom is still defined in material terms: the transcendental qualities of mind are still reduced to matter even though, in Dennett's words, we have a little "elbow room." While a functional organism can freely act, it cannot transcend, or in Hegelian terms, sublate (aufheben) its physical thrownness. Thus, within this context, freedom is still reduced to a physical ontology. For Hegel, freedom is among other things freedom from natural determination. We are free but we are natural beings; thus freedom is the process of transcending nature while incorporating it in its spiritual embodiment. Having attained freedom from its mere natural, necessarily determined corporeality, Geist is actively free to determine itself as a dynamic, intelligible self-articulated complex whole.

A sophisticated materialist view claims to allow for conscious experience, but disavows the notion that an ontology of consciousness may be purported to exist above or even equiprimordially along with neurophysiological properties of the brain. For Dretske and Dennett, we are an elaborately designed and malleable machine in which we are also the designers, yet the blueprints must conform to natural laws. When followed through to its end, the mind is ultimately explained by appeal to material and efficient causal-evolutionary forces that have their teleology in substance. Thus, in the end, we are not autonomous free agents because substance teleology is confined to the formal characteristics of a pre-determined design. While self-assigned meaning as a mental property has causal powers, meaning is ultimately a pattern of neurons firing in the brain or a realized state in the biological machine. Mental activity is merely the product of a physical apparatus. Consciousness, meaning, and intentionality are merely neurological structures and processes, and the 'I' is the system itself. The human being is still a thing, a complex thing, but nevertheless, a physical system. The true test for materialism is to explain, if it can, how matter can have freely self-directed constituting agency. Agency from the physicalist standpoint is not free, for it is only the product and succession of material and efficient properties of the brain.

A Word from Physics

What is particularly interesting is that those social scientists and philosophers of mind discussed above seem to be unaware of the recent discoveries in the natural sciences (see Anderson & Stein, 1987; Atmanspacher, 1997; Atmanspacher, Amann, & Müller-Herold, 1999; Penrose, 1989; Primas, 1993). Many thoughtful scholars in experimental and theoretical physics as well as biophysics, biochemistry, genetics, and mathematics oppose reductionism on ontological, methodological, and epistemological levels (Yates, 1987). Because the procedures, observations, terms, and patterns of explanation in some sciences are entirely unconnectable to those of other disciplines (Ayala, 1987), reductive strategies that wish to collapse one branch of science into another is neither possible nor desirous. For example, physicists Philip Anderson and Daniel Stein (1987) compared dissipative structures with thermodynamic equilibrium systems and conclude that complex physical systems exhibit emergent properties unrelated to those of their constituents. While higher order novelties and complexities arise out of simpler events, such complexifications are hardly reducible to their previous states.

Following the work of Hans Primas (1993, 1994), Otto Rössler (1994) has also provided support for a "parallelism" between phenomenology and science. In his assessment, endophysics offers a two-level interpretation of objective reality (endo and exo) that preserves the dualism inherent in both Cartesian and Kantian philosophy. While the endo-questions pertinent to quantum mechanics may be solved, the exo level remains, with qualifications, directly inaccessible. This is why physicists speak of probabilities rather than locality (see Gustafson, 1999; Sudarshan, 1999) and of correlations rather than causation (Atmanspacher, Amann, & Müller-Herold, 1999).

Harald Atmanspacher and Frederick Kronz (1999) further contend that the multilevel structure of generalized quantum theories are too simplistic if epistemic and ontic elements are considered on the same level of description. Following Quine (1969b), they conclude that ontological descriptions are relative to the conceptual scheme one espouses. Because both mind and matter are emergent domains of description that are fundamentally symmetrical, they further speculate that the distinction between mental and physical polarities becomes irrelevant.

It is unfortunate that such ardent materialists are not acquainted with the advancements made by the natural sciences and their subsequent implications, such as the momentous discovery of the energetic stratification of material interactions; if they were, the whole reductionist enterprise would be recognized for what it is: an ideological artifact that is scientifically indefensible. These arguments radically change the whole issue. Until the relation between quanta, mind, and matter is examined from a holistic paradigm (see Shimony, 1999), the illusion of materialism will likely persist.

Death of the Self

One of the most disturbing consequences of the materialist position is that the notion of the Self dissolves. In the spirit of Nietzsche, "The Self is Dead!," and materialism killed it. Essentially, this view is commensurate with a Buddhist or Humean view of the self--there is none, only sensations and impressions impinging on the senses in a fleeting moment. For Hume, there is no 'I' directing mentation. There is only the theater of the mind where thoughts are cast by natural laws and where self-reflection is only second order perceptions. The self is merely an illusion. Thus, free will and any sense of personal identity is non-existent. In Dennett's (1991) words, we "spin a self," or as Skinner would contend, we are only operantly conditioned to believe in a self. The 'I' is just a social construction or invention of language: we are a collection of dynamic mental properties and perceptions in flux, that's all.

Whether one conceives of the self in the tradition of Descartes' cogito as the 'I' that resides behind the cognizer, or the Kantian transcendental unity of apperception as the nominal, enduring, unified unifier, or Hegel's notion of subjective spirit (Geist), or Sartre's notion of the self as radical freedom, to the Freudian ego (Ich) as a self-directed synthesizing agent--the distinctive psychical processes and properties of consciousness, not to mention the unconscious, are dismissed from the materialist framework. While a physical system can be dynamically organized and functionally sophisticated, in the end, the organism is doing the thinking and behaving, not the self. Materialists would contend, however, that the organism is the self. But it is precisely this definitional issue that becomes problematic. The notion of the self plays a great role in human value practices and should not be conceived merely as a physical entity. Human experience, personal identity, character formation, and selfhood simply cannot be reduced to atoms and sub-atomic particles without losing the integrity of freedom and an ontologically transcendental self.

Furthermore, if you are looking for the possibility of a personal afterlife, materialism offers very little comfort. Not only are free will and the self eliminated, but materialism is consequentially a fundamental atheism. Spiritual transcendence of the soul or personality, or the possibility of an afterlife are not tenable within the materialist framework. If the mind or psyche is nothing more than its material substrate (merely active particles), then the substance would cease to exist upon its physical death. The soul as psychical substance could not exist in disembodied form, hence death of the organism is death of the soul. As Graham (1993) tells us, if "the soul is something mental and the soul survives bodily death, whereas the brain fails to survive, then there is no such thing as a soul" (p. 129). Unless by some miraculous means, such as the possibility that physical decomposition could be reconstituted in another physical medium--the likelihood of which is close to nil, the soul would not exist. It would be virtually impossible to rebuild and reconnect the millions of neural pathways destroyed by physical decay, such as in the case of brain trauma or dementia. And if this were possible, such as in some Star Trek episode, the question of sustained personal identity would remain equivocal. Reconstituted matter by definition would no longer be identical to itself. A duplicated self would not be the same self. For materialists, all natural phenomena eventually pass out of existence and return to an eternal, primordial material ground in an eternal transformation of matter, so wave 'good bye' to a personal afterlife. Simply put, spiritualism, supernaturalism, immaterialism, disembodiment, transcendentalism, and any appeal to mystical experience, revelation, or faith are untenable hypotheses.

There is something so counter intuitive to this claim, that human consciousness, or the self, personal identity, or soul (either theologically or non-theologically conceived) is not a transcendental agent with psychic properties and attributes. Materialism assumes that what is real is only what appears and that it can be objectively verified as tangible fact. But the whole notion of the spiritual is by definition that which cannot be empirically measured or quantified. It is by virtue of the fact that we have no direct epistemic access to the transcendental properties of the mind that we must posit its ontological status. In fact for Hegel (1830), there is nothing which we are more certain of than the spiritual by virtue of the fact that we posit it.

Even if we were to concede that the mind ceases to exist upon the moment of physical death, this would not rule out the presence of Self, teleology, agency, free will, choice, and the spiritual dimensions of the human condition. The phenomenology of the lived experience--extending to all facets of human motivation, desire, emotion, and rational thought--cannot be adequately captured by the rigidly reductive language and ontological pronouncements that characterize some branches of natural science. Philosophical, historical, cultural, aesthetic, and psychological hermeneutics, to name just a few, allow for a plurality of interpretations to resonate among privileged discourse on the nature of selfhood. Materialism simply does not address the human aspect as a dynamic self-articulated totality or complex whole.

It appears that materialists must anchor ontology to something physical or tangible as a verification of their quest for certainty. Nagel (1974) nicely makes the point that materialists have a penchant for describing mental phenomena in physical terms as operating in the service of objectivity. Yet by espousing this viewpoint in the name of objectivity, it takes us further away from the real nature of consciousness (the subjective lived experience) rather than bringing us closer to it. One does not need to be reminded that the object of 'objectivity' is always interpreted through the 'mind's eye,' that of the subject. Kant (1781) also reminds us of the limits to the possibility of epistemic certainty: we can never know the noumena directly, only through the translation of our senses mediated by rational understanding. Thus, materialism deceives itself by espousing a 'God's eye' view of the universe in its attempt to logically account for all phenomena. Within this framework of natural science, such presumption about reality becomes manifested in the belief that if one can account for every particle, one can (at least in principle) accurately control and predict the world. Science appears as the touchstone for Truth, when in fact, science is just one appearance among many appearances. For Kant (1781), any physicalist attempt to make ontological claims about the "thing-in-itself" (Ding an sich) is fallacious: by definition this is unknowable, simply unverifiable, an unprovable tenet, hence an open indeterminate question--the very claim in contemporary physics (see Primas, 1993, 1994; Rössler, 1994).

Value Judgements Concerning Social Practices

Because materialism is over-identified with a scientific epistemology, there is a tacit prejudice that the human being is a biological machine which one can control, predict, and manipulate. While science and medicine have provided and continue to provide humanity with knowledge and technology that drastically improves the quality of life, there is an inherent danger in the tendency to view the human being only as a biological organism. Within this context, there is a medicalization or objectification of the human subject. The hazard in this treatment of the subject as an object is that it may lead to social, political, and scientific practices that fail to account for the dynamic psychological complexity of mental life and the existential human needs inherent to conscious experience. This biased naturalistic view may condone various professional practices in medicine, psychiatry, and the social sciences. We have already seen how the medical model of psychiatry has usurped psychological approaches to the treatment of certain types of mental illnesses. For example, Prozac is the salient choice mode of intervention for depression over psychotherapy--assuming that all forms of depression have a biological correlate which is confused with etiology, hence are physically caused. This is simply erroneous.(4) The danger to such medical practices is that people get the message that all they need to do is take a pill and they will be happy. Physical interventions and psycho-pharmacological treatments may be appropriate for some medical or psychiatric conditions, but certainly not all. Such objectification of the human being may potentially justify myriad ethically dubious practices (e.g., fetal tissue research, euthanasia, physician assisted suicide, genetic and human cloning). The reduction of the phenomenology of consciousness could further lead to an invalidation of uniquely subjective lived existential experience. The human being is not just an organism to be manipulated by science, rather is a person to be acknowledged and valued. The medicalization and clinical depiction of the human being seems to lack a degree of empathy, concernful solicitude, and careful insight into the array of human experiences that cannot be reduced or explained away with technical jargon or physicalistic nomenclature.

In his refutation of modern scientific materialism, Alfred North Whitehead (1925) charges physicalist accounts of mind and nature with the Fallacy of Simple Location or Misplaced Concreteness; i.e. the error of objectifying a high-order abstraction as a concrete entity. Whitehead points out the confusion and misguided conclusions that occur when levels of abstraction are reduced to simply located quantitative properties of matter. This attitude is essentially the belief that what comprises the basic elements of the real is the simply located particle. In quoting a poem from Wordsworth, Whitehead shows that the antiseptic language of science can never capture the feeling of nature that is encountered in the lived experience:

We forget how strained and paradoxical is the view of nature which modern science imposes on our thoughts. Wordsworth, to the height of genius, expresses the concrete facts of our apprehension, facts which are distorted in the scientific analysis. Is it not possible that the standardised concepts of science are only valid within narrow limitations, perhaps too narrow for science itself (1925, p. 84)?

If we were to ask a botanist to describe the essence of a flower, s/he would in all likelihood discuss its physical and chemical composition such as its reproductive organs, its petals, sepals, pistil, stamens, its anther and filament, etc. But if we were to consult a poet such as Wordsworth: "And 'tis my faith that every flower, / Enjoys the air it breathes" ("Lines Written in Early Spring," lines 11-12; see Kraus, 1998, p. 25), we are forced to confront a different perspective of reality. Are we to assume that science holds a privileged depiction of nature, such as the nature of a flower? Which one is more real? As useful as it may be in certain contexts, materialist explanations may only offer a limited glimpse into understanding the essence of mind. The aesthetic, the moral, the feelings that comprise the quality of lived experience are perspectives of being that can never be adequately explained by reductive science.

Another potentially dehumanizing aspect of the materialist agenda is to advocate a change in linguistic communication practices that emphasize physical description. For example, Paul Churchland proposes that we adopt a new language to describe brain states rather than conscious experiences. This is further echoed by Smart (1962) who states ". . . it would make sense to talk of an experience in terms appropriate to physical processes" (p.173). Why? Why do we need a conceptual and social change in language and communication practices? What pragmatic usefulness would it have for people to talk about and communicate their complex cognitive, emotive, and psychological experiences in physically descriptive language? How could it facilitate arriving at a more accurate picture of inner reality? Instead of saying, "I love you," we would say, "My neurons are firing in sector 14.2 of my left frontal lobe." Is love really like a heatwave (see Levin, 1986)? Churchland (1981) even goes so far to propose that we eliminate current social language practices and replace them with an alternative language that would require monumental social and educational changes, not to mention experimental surgery on human beings. He suggests we could "construct a new system of verbal communication entirely distinct from natural language" (p. 220). Such a proposal would require massive changes in the way the world thinks, communicates, and operates. In addition, he proposes placing a "transducer for implantation at some site in the brain" (p. 221).

To me this is clearly an unethical proposal and probably motivated out of the need to generate controversy in the service of personal narcissism and/or ideology. Experimentation on humans? -- as if everyone would be a willing participant. The ramifications of such a practice would result in a complete alteration in the way people think, talk, and perceive reality; thus personality, identity, and one's sense of self would be radically mutated. In essence, people would no longer be who they previously were: it would be tantamount to turning people into machines.

In his essay, "Quining Qualia," Dennett (1988) also wants to get rid of the word 'qualia' and redefine the theory of consciousness within a materialist framework. He claims because subjective states have "ineffable" properties, they are only accessible from the first person viewpoint and therefore cannot be detected by physical strategies. While he allows for conscious experience, he is denying any special attributes of qualia as lived experience; the only thing experienced is alterations in brain states. The phenomena of conscious subjectivity that we know as our experience of the world is only the brain undergoing various neuro-chemical changes which cannot be directly observed or communicated by the subject. While Dennett is arguing against essentialism, his position appears to be essentially reductive. If we are nothing but brain states, then we have a fixed essence in the form of physical organization despite dynamic complexities in its transformation and evolution. Once again, consciousness has no ontological status apart from its substance.

The materialist platform appears to ignore the very qualities of individuality and the phenomenology of experience, if not deny the social and psychological motivations behind our language practices. As a society, we strive for pluralism not singularity. Language practices are rich in diversity and multiplicity and cannot be made to conform to rigid and narrowly-minded practices characteristic of reductionistic strategies. Part of the very nature of human psychology is to resist such restrictions on human expression: the creative, aesthetic, and generative powers of imagination and human desire would be sacrificed to an antiseptic oppressive regime characteristic of a totalitarian state. What would we do with a language that would require intensive specialized training? And how would this be implemented and enforced? Not only is such a proposal ridiculously impractical, it would do nothing but stifle the diversity and idiosyncracy of human experience. We have the responsibility to apply science in a humanistic fashion, not pass value judgements on authentic ways of being.

Materialism poses further problems surrounding the nature of value inquiry. How could values and ideals (as well as the broader transcendental dimensions of consciousness) be reduced merely to biology, or even in some more extreme cases, physical particles alone that, if properly measured through empirical means, inform us how we ought to think and reason? This is particularly imperative when addressing the question of morality. Can moral responsibility be boiled down to biology? Kim (1994) also questions whether "ethical expressions are definable, or reducible . . . in terms of 'descriptive' or 'naturalistic' expressions" (p. 242). How can moral behavior and ethical responsibility be reduced to matter? Behavior genetics is a highly controversial and problematic science for it attempts to explain human psychological functioning from the standpoint of evolutionary biology. Despite our discovery of increased genetic detail that has greatly enriched our understanding of human biology and evolution, it has done nothing to resolve the questions concerning differences between human values and social practices (Shipman, 1994). Dreyfus and Nelkin (1992) have gone so far to attribute "genetic essentialism" to criminality. Imagine this legal defense: "I couldn't help it, my genes made me do it!" If this were the case, social, legal, and political-congregational systems would be confronted with a diffusion of personal responsibility that places the locus of control on factors independent of the self. While I am not concerned that materialism offers any threat to the moral responsibility and actions of human beings, I am concerned that the metaphysical integrity of freedom, selfhood, and the principle of morality itself could become sullied.

Toward Psychic Holism

Throughout this project, I have attempted to delineate five dangers of materialism characteristic of the naturalistic and physically reductive paradigms within the cognitive sciences and the philosophy of mind today. Perhaps the main motive of materialism is simply this: If you say all mental events are just physical events, then you do not have a mystery--the mind-body conundrum is solved. Searle (1994) summarizes this position: "The famous mind-body problem, . . . has a simple solution . . . Here it is: mental phenomena are caused by neurophysiological processes in the brain and are themselves features of the brain" (p. 277). This is reductionism at its finest.

The claim that the mind is nothing but the brain is a dogmatic assertion that attributes ontological primacy to physical states over mental processes and properties. In short, the materialist holds a fallacious and simplistic view of causality, denies free agency of the self, and increasing portrays the human being as a clinical object. The ethical implications of such approaches in medical and social-political practices may potentially threaten the integrity of individuality and collective identity which may further lead to an invalidation and/or empathic impasse regarding human difference and understanding.

Furthermore, within this context, the transcendental features of psychic reality--emotive, aesthetic, spiritual, moral, and religious experience--are trivialized. Not only is the quality of the lived experience truncated, materialism consequently neglects the function and role the concept of self assumes for human value. The value and concept of our sense of self serves a fundamental structural and functional role in identity, ethical responsibility, and self-representation. The transcendental qualities of experience and selfhood are in danger of becoming displaced if we are to view the human condition solely from naturalistic paradigms. While the boon of materialism is scientific, medical, technological, and consequently social advancement, the bane is the demise of the self as a complex integrated whole.

Compatiblist interpretations may offer a promissory reconciliation of the mind-body problem through the unification of material and psychic embodiment. One such champion of compatiblism is Alfred North Whitehead who, in his endeavor to bridge the Cartesian rift between res extensa and res cognitans, offers a speculative metaphysics that unifies physical and mental realities. For Whitehead (1929), the universe is comprised of incalculable "societies" of "actual entities" or "actual occasions" that are interconnected "drops of experience, complex and interdependent" (p. 18). In the tradition of German Idealism that conceives of Geist as pure activity, Whitehead sees mind as the interpenetration of events constituting psychic reality. Although Whitehead characterizes the "dipolar" constitution of the mind in terms of its physicality and mentality, which permits him to avoid the "bifurcation of nature," the polarities of the psyche are ontologically undifferentiated, thus allowing for the unification of the mind and the body as a cohesive whole. Following Heraclitus' dictum: "Everything flows" (panta hrei), Hegel's dialectic of Spirit, or Whitehead's process reality, mind is a process of becoming.

Psychic holism constitutes the belief in the multifarious existence and interdependence of the intrapsychic, mental, somatic, and materialistic processes that comprise the individual's relation to the world and life. This philosophical position is exemplified by Carl Jung's notion of the unus mundus as "one unitary world." Adopted from various schools of Gnosticism, neo-Platonism, and Medieval philosophy,

the idea of the unus mundus is founded on the assumption that the multiplicity of the empirical world rests on an underlying unity . . .; everything divided and different belongs to one and the same world . . . That even the psychic world, which is so extraordinarily different from the physical world, does not have its roots outside the one cosmos is evident from the undeniable fact that causal connections exist between the psyche and the body which point to their underlying unitary nature . . . The background of our empirical world thus appears to be in fact a unus mundus (Jung, 1956, p. 538).

The emphasis on psychical holism allows for the multiplicity of psychological, material, spiritual, aesthetic, mystical, transcendental, and transpersonal conceptions of mind to flourish as equally viable ways of articulating the dynamic structures, experiences, and processes that underlie mental life. Within holistic and compatiblist paradigms, the nature of the Self, freedom, choice, personal autonomy, and responsibility are sheltered from the bane of physical reduction. Psychic reality is an unus mundus, and like the mandala, signifies the unity and integrated wholeness of the undifferentiated ontology that we know as mind.
 

References

Anderson, P.W., & Stein, D.L. (1987). Broken symmetry, emergent properties, dissipative structures, life: Are they related? In F. E. Yates (Ed.), Self-organizing systems: The emergence of order, 445-457. New York: Plenum Press.

Arieti, S., & Bemporad, J. (1978). Severe and mild depression. New York: Basic Books.

Armstrong, D.M. (1968). A materialist theory of mind. London: Routledge, Kegan & Paul.

Atmanspacher, H. (1997). Cartesian cut, Heisenberg cut, and the concept of complexity. World Futures, 49, 321-343.

Atmanspacher, H., Amann, A., & Müller-Herold, U. (Eds.) (1999). On quanta, mind, and matter: Hans Primas in context. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Atmanspacher, H. & Kronz, F. (1999). Relative onticity. In H Atmanspacher, A. Amann, & U. Müller-Herold (Eds.), On quanta, mind, and matter: Hans Primas in context, 203-216. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Ayala, F.J. (1987). Biological reductionism: The problems and some answers. In F. E. Yates (Ed.), Self-organizing systems: The emergence of order, 315-324. New York: Plenum Press.

Bechtel, W. (1988). Philosophy of mind: An overview for cognitive science. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

Bitsakis, E. (1993). Scientific realism. Science and Society, 57 (2), 160-193.

Churchland, P.M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67-90.

Dancy, J. & Sosa, E. (1992). A companion to epistemology. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.

Dennett, D.C. (1981). True believers: The intentional strategy and why its works. In A.F. Heath (Ed.), Scientific explanation: Papers based on Herbert Spencer lectures given in the University of Oxford, 37-61. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Dennett, D.C. (1984). Elbow room. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Dennett, D.C. (1988). Quining qualia. In A. Marcel and E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science, 42-77. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Dennett, D.C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.

Descartes, R. (1984). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Trans.), The philosophical writings of Descartes, Vol. II, 1-62. New York: Cambridge University Press. Original work published in 1641.

Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behaviour: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

Dreyfus, R.C. & Nelkin, D. (1992). The jurisprudence of genetics. Vanderbilt Law Review, 45 (2), 313-348.

Flew, A. (1984). A dictionary of philosophy: Revised second edition. New York: St. Martin's Press.

Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences, or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28, 97-115.

Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosematics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

Fodor, J. (1998). In Critical condition: Polemical essays on cognitive science and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

Freud, S. (1900). The Interpretation of dreams. In James Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 5. London: Hogarth Press.

Freud, S. (1916-1917). Introductory lectures on psycho-analysis. In James Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 15. London: Hogarth Press.

Freud, S. (1917). Mourning and melancholia. In James Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 14. London: Hogarth Press.

Graham, G. (1993). Philosophy of mind: An introduction. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Gustafson, K. (1999). The geometry of quantum probabilities. In H Atmanspacher, A. Amann, & U. Müller-Herold (Eds.), On quanta, mind, and matter: Hans Primas in context, 54-77. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Hanly, C. (1979). Existentialism and psychoanalysis. New York: International Universities Press.

Hegel, G.W.F. (1991). The encyclopaedia logic, Vol.1 of the Encyclopaedia of the philosophical sciences. T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting, & H.S. Harris (Trans.). (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company). Original work published in 1830.

Horgan, T. (1994). Nonreductive materialism. In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds), The mind-body problem, 190-207. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Hume, D. (1961). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. In R. Taylor (Ed.), The empiricists, 307-430. Garden City, NY: Dolphin Books. Original work published in 1748.

Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127-136.

Jung, C.G. (1970). Mysterium Coniunctionis. In H. Read, M. Fordham, & G. Adler (Eds.); R.F.C. Hull (Trans.), Collected Works of C.G. Jung, Vol. 14.. London: Routledge & Kagan Paul; Princeton: Princeton University Press. Original work published in 1956.

Kant, I (1965). Critique of Pure Reason. N.K. Smith (Trans.). New York: St. Martin's Press. Original work published in 1781.

Kim, J. (1994). The myth of nonreductive materialism. In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds.), The mind-body problem, 208-222. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Kohut, H. (1977). The restoration of the self . New York: International Universities Press.

Kraus, E.M. (1998). The metaphysics of experience. New York: Fordham University Press.

Levin, J. (1986). Could love be like a heatwave? Physicalism and the subjective character of experience. Philosophical Studies, 49 (2), 245-261.

Levin, M.E. (1979). Metaphysics and the mind-body problem. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.

Lewis, D. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63, 17-25.

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, LXXXIII (4), 435-450.

Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor's new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Place, U.T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? The British Journal of Psychology, 47, 42-51.

Post, J.F. (1987). The faces of existence: An essay in nonreductive metaphysics. New York: Cornell University Press.

Post, J.F. (1991). Metaphysics. New York: Paragon.

Post, J.F. (1995). "Global" supervenient determination: Too permissive? In Elias Savellos & Mit Yalcin (Eds.), Essays on supervenience. 73-100. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Primas, H. (1993). The Cartesian cut, the Heisenberg cut, and disentangled observers. In K.V. Laurikainen & C. Montonen (Eds.), Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics 1992: The Copenhagen Interpretation and Wolfgang Pauli, 31-56. Sinapore: World Scientific.

Primas, H. (1994). Endo- and exotheories of matter. In H. Atmanspacher & G.J. Dalenoort (Eds.), Inside versus Outside, 23-49. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion, 156-170. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Putnam, H. (1975). The nature of mental states. In Philosophical papers, vol.2, mind, language, and reality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

Putnam, H. (1983). Why reason can't be naturalized. In P.K. Moser & A. Vandernat (Eds.), Human knowledge, 355-365, 1987. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Quine, W.V. (1969a). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

Quine, W.V. (1969b). Ontological relativity. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

Rössler, O.E. (1994). Endophysics -- Descartes taken seriously. In H. Atmanspacher & G.J. Dalenoort (Eds.), Inside versus Outside, 50-64. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

Searle, J. (1994). What's wrong with the philosophy of mind? In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds.), The mind-body problem, 290-311. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Shimony, A. (1999). Holism. In H. Atmanspacher, A. Amann, & U. Müller-Herold (Eds.), On quanta, mind, and matter: Hans Primas in context, 86-99. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Shipman, P. (1994). The evolution of racism. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Smart, J.J.C. (1962). Sensations and brain processes. In V.C Chappell (Ed.), The Philosophy of mind, 19-36. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

Sober, E. (1985). Putting the function back into functionalism. Synthese, 64 (2), 165-193.

Stich, S.P. (1994). What is a theory of mental representation? In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds.), The mind-body problem, 321-341. Oxford: Blackwell.

Sudarshan, E.C.G. (1999). Probability and quantum dynamics. In H. Atmanspacher, A. Amann, & U. Müller-Herold (Eds.), On quanta, mind, and matter: Hans Primas in context, 176-191. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Teller, P. (1983). A poor man's guide to supervenience and determination. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 22, Supplement, 147.

Thalberg, I. (1983). Misconceptions of mind and freedom. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

Vendler, Zeno (1994). The ineffable soul. In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds.), The mind-body problem, 197-214. Oxford, England: Blackwell.

Vollmer, G. (1975). Evolutionary epistemology. Stuttgart: Hirzel.

Warner, R. (1994). In defense of dualism. In R. Warner and T. Szubka (Eds.), The mind-body problem, 215-229. Oxford, Engalnd: Blackwell.

Whitehead, A.N. (1925). Science and the modern world. New York: Free Press.

Whitehead, A.N. (1929). Process and reality, Corrected Edition, D.R. Griffin & D.W. Sherburne (Eds). New York: Free Press.

Wuketits, F. (1990). Evolutionary epistemology. New York: SUNY Press.

Yates, F. E. (Ed.) (1987). Self-organizing systems: The emergence of order. New York: Plenum Press.

Notes

1. 1. There is a spectrum of doctrines which call themselves realists ranging from: naive realism, direct realism, intuitive realism, natural realism, critical realism, blind realism, scientific realism, metaphysical realism, epistemic realism, medieval realism, radical realism, Platonic realism, semantic realism, internal realism, realism with a capital R and realism with a small r, sophisticated realism, commonsense realism, pragmatic realism, ontological realism, and revisionary realism (see Bitsakis, 1993 for a review). Traditionally, the issue of realism is a metaphysical question. If we are to assume the historical position in the tradition of Aristotle, then realism is the belief that objects in the material world exist independent of consciousness and do not require thought to sustain their existence. In other words, they would exist despite whether or not they could be thought or perceived. Some materialists would qualify their claim by arguing that metaphysical realism is unverifiable, thus a meaningless proposition. Instead they may adopt a critical realist position, assuming that there must be something behind the appearance of natural objects of investigation, or else they adopt phenomenalism: reality is only that which appears.

2. The chief difference between behaviorism and materialism is that behaviorism does not posit complex intervening mental structures, processes, or strategies that govern or mediate one's responses to stimuli, while materialism does. Contemporary materialism offers a more sophisticated physicalist theory that does not explain cognition and behavior in solely mechanistic or environmentally conditioned terms.

3. Davidson is following Quine's thesis of indeterminacy of translation which claims that ascriptions of propositional attitudes are relative to schemes of translation. See Quine's (1969b) Ontological Relativity and Levin (1979) for discussion.

4. There is a great body of literature, primarily in psychoanalysis and cognitive-behavioral psychology, that denotes the psychological etiology of various forms of depression ranging from bereavement, responses to loss, death, separation, and divorce, insecure attachments, emotional detachment and abandonment from love objects, inverted aggression, persecutory and self-punitive admonitions, to characterological forms of depression commensurate with a structurally depleted self (Arieti & Bemporad, 1978; Freud, 1917; Kohut, 1977).